November 14, 2022
These are notes that I found on
my outdated but useful AlphaSmart word processor. The reading and notes are a
response to the Secret History of Western
Esotericism podcast (SHWEP), which I began listening to in the autumn of
2020. Therefore, the notes were written after that, and likely in 2021. I will reproduce
the text here—as an artifact—with only a few grammatical corrections and
expansions for clarity. The latter are indicated in brackets.
***
Listening to the SHWEP has
prompted me to return to Plato’s texts after many years. Actually, the detailed
discussions on the podcast have inspired me to read Platonic texts I had never
read before (i.e., the Parmenides and the Timaeus). I have been struck by how
holistic Plato is when it comes to bridging the gap between rational and
extra-rational modes of knowing, let us [call them]. [What follows will be]
overly schematic in order to highlight some points I find significant.
From the perspective of
intellectual history (that is, from the perspective of what might be presented
in a course with “intellectual history” in the title), Plato comes across as
the father of rational philosophizing in the traditions stemming from the
Greeks. A nod is given to the pre-Socratics. I take it that this is roughly how
Plato appears in the analytical cannon, at least as a necessary link in the
chain leading to Aristotelian logic. I do not think that this is entirely inaccurate.
Nevertheless, I have been struck
by all the ways that Plato describes extra-rational inspiration impinging upon
the person, and therefore impacting discursive philosophy itself. In fact, he
seems to be always trying to integrate the extra-rational into the latter, as
if making it an essential moment of the whole.
Lokilech, CC BY-SA 3.0 <http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/>, via Wikimedia Commons
"Diagram of the sheep's liver found near Piacenza with Etruscan inscriptions"—Wikipedia article on the Haruspex
For example, long passages in the
Timaeus are concerned with what we might
call the relationship between human consciousness and the body. For all the
talk of Aristotle being the naturalist, these passages of Plato’s would not be
wholly out of place in Aristotle’s De Anima.
At any rate, Plato [describes]
how the higher, rational part of the soul communicates with the lower parts,
which are more connected to the organism.
Interestingly (and this is very
much in keeping with divinatory [practice] across the Near East [and
Mediterranean worlds]), the liver figures as the mediator between the higher
and lower parts of the soul, and is the site of divination.
Plato says that it is the lower
soul which receives divine inspiration, as evidenced by the fact that sleeping,
mad, intoxicated, etc., people are more likely to be oracular. In other words, inspiration
of this sort corresponds to a paralysis of the rational functions. He seems to [say]
that, in a certain sense, this kind of knowledge is actually higher, but to be
of any use, it [must] be dealt with by the rational intellect. It is the sober
man who can interpret an oracle, not the intoxicated one who delivers the
oracle.
This whole scheme preserves a
kind of hierarchy where the rational soul must be in charge. But [the rational
soul] is dependent on the inspirations that are received in the lower soul and
sent up via the liver.
Now, the talk about divination
parallels Plato’s passages on poets. In fact, he often pairs these two concepts
(divination and poetry). At least one scholar (I will have to look for this
article), argues that—in the corpus as a whole—Plato refers to divination as
often as he does poetry. However, because of the preoccupations of humanistic
scholars, Plato’s views on poetry have been treated at length, whereas the
subject of divination has barely been broached. This is the result of modern
prejudices. Clearly, people in literature departments have been very interested
in what Plato has to say about poetry and poets.
[The article is Plato and Divination by Peter T. Struck. The abstract states: “Plato uses the idea of divinatory knowledge as a metaphorical descriptor for a variety of kinds of daytime, waking knowing. What unites these examples is that they all include discussion of a kind of knowing that cannot account for itself, and that is tentative, imagistic and non-discursive. These metaphorical uses can further be illuminated by his more detailed discussion of divinatory knowledge itself in Timeaus.”]
But the conception is much the
same. It is well known that Plato is concerned about the tendency of poets to
distort the truth. [Whether there is a systematic “Platonic poetics is another
question, see Stephen
Halliwell.] He does not, however, say that they are always wrong. At least
in the Timaeus and other texts I have looked at over the past few months, he
says that poets often do hit upon the truth, but, like oracles, they do not know
where it comes from. They are deficient in that they cannot account for the
truths through discursive argumentation. Put another way, in order to fully
deploy the truths brought out by poets or oracles, discursive reason is needed.
It is notable how often this
happens in real time in the dialogues. Sometimes Socrates says, “I divine that,”
or something else indicating that he has been suddenly inspired. He cannot
immediately account for the knowledge. He then says, roughly, “Now let’s put
this idea to the test through rational discourse.” It is reason that determines
whether the inspiration is true or useful (hence the hierarchy is preserved, if
we can say that there is a kind of map of human faculties in Plato), but
without the extra-rational inspiration, reason would not have had an object on
which to operate.
No comments:
Post a Comment